Marx’s objections to credit theories of money

نویسنده

  • Anitra Nelson
چکیده

right, or the power of demanding services in general, which may, or may not be commodities’ (Ibid: 35). The most advanced form of such transferable debt had no intrinsic value, typically paper, so the intrinsic value of silver or gold as money was ‘secondary’ (Ibid: 45). Gold and silver were only the most civilised of a lineage of representatives of labour, including shells and chocolate — clearly ideal symbols in contrast to Marx’s material emphasis. For Macleod, currency referred to or acted as a necessarily variable measure of value. He emphasised that barter involved a numeraire. Citing historical instances where the measure was distinct from the currency, Macleod saw no necessary correspondence between the material and value of currency. On this latter point he lik M i i h i However, while Macleod defined ‘exchangable value’ in terms of the relative value of the labour involved in production (Ibid: 22), he derided Ricardo’s notion of cost of production (1856:lix). Marx (1859: 61–2) in turn defended the association Ricardo made between exchange-value and labour-time from criticisms of bourgeois economists, including Macleod. Macleod (1855: 78) regarded price as the result of a struggle between suppliers and purchasers. His obscure and simplistic formulas equated: 1) ‘Exchangable value’ with ‘Labor’ divided by the ‘Quantity’ (of the product of labour) multiplied by ‘Utility’, and 2) ‘Price’ with the ‘Intensity of Service Rendered’ divided by the ‘Power of Buyer over Seller’ (Ibid: 50, 77). While such views clearly put Macleod beyond the pale for Marx, he made other references, for instance to labour and the circuit of capital, that were more consistent with Marx’s models in Capital II (1885). Macleod (1855: liv) insisted that money was ‘the symbolical store of unexpended labor’ in contrast to commodities, ‘the produce of expended labor’. He (1856: xliv) was adamant that buying to consume depended on ‘past skill, judgement, and industry’ whereas buying to sell or to invest implied credit or ‘future skill, judgement, and industry’. Macleod (1856: lii) accused Ricardo of mistaking credit for capital and capital for commodities: ‘so long as a man believes that Capital or money represents commodities, he can have no true idea of monetary science’. Macleod (1855: 262) argued that currency became capital. In his terms: The primary, genuine, and exclusive meaning...of Capital, is the accumulated savings of Labor, and its symbol is money. (Macleod 1856: xlv) Such points are likely to have interested Marx, who integrated various ideas of how labour related to capital and money into his circuits of capital (P–C–M...) even though the money commodity had a place in the Capital II reproduction schemas. Schumpeter has stressed that despite Macleod’s advances as a theortical cartallist, he remained a practical metallist (Skaggs 1997: 113). Macleod (1855: 261) argued that bank credit was based on bank capital and that this capacity was critical for capitalist development. However, Macleod (1856: 337) criticised Lawism and the Bank of England’s real bills doctrine because he believed that currency could not be created in unrealistic amounts but must, in terms of its value, refer back to a substance i h l i l lik ld Thi did b h ff i correspondence for convertibility and he suggested that competing banks would conveniently limit the quantity of paper currency circulating (Macleod 1855: 402–5). Given his own theory reflected reality, Marx probably regarded this practical qualification a deficiency. Given the obscurity and unpopularity of Macleod’s ideas and the hyperbole of his text it is understandable why Marx found his works spurious and commended them little. Superficially there was a correspondence in the practical views of Marx and Macleod regarding the ultimate function of, say gold, to anchor the system. However, Marx developed a complex concept of a money commodity that was associated with his labour theory of value while Macleod remained adamant that the primary quality of money was as a valueless claim to future products or services. The main direction of Macleod’s analysis did not escape Marx (1859: 143n) who averred that ‘he misinterprets the most elementary economic relations to such an extent that that he asserts that money in general arises from its most advanced form, that is means of payment’. The inference was to Marx’s ordered presentation: primarily money was a measure of value; secondarily money was a means of exchange that included state currency; and combining these functions in at a tertiary level enabled a universal material of contracts or means of payment including credit monies. 2.2 Bishop George Berkeley In The Querist (1735–37), Bishop George Berkeley asked questions at the base of credit theories of money, i.e.: [Query] 35. Whether power to command the industry of others be not real wealth? And whether money be not in truth tickets or tokens for conveying and recording such power, and whether it be of great consequence what materials the tickets are made of? His vision for the Irish was to achieve modest self-sufficiency by hard work and frugality (Queries 421, 542). He proposed that labour was ‘the true source of wealth’ and that human industry provided money with value (Queries 4, 38). In fact money was singularly useful in developing industry that implied trade (Queries 5, 30). Berkeley doubted the benefit of external trade and argued for a national bank and mint to develop an Irish monetary system for domestic circulation and investment. His approach to price and value focussed on the superficial level of market demand and supply and exchange values (Query 24). As such, he related monies of account to exchange value, asking: 25. Whether the terms crown, livre, pound sterling, etc., are not to be considered as exponents or denominations of such proportion? And whether gold, silver, and paper are not tickets or counters for reckoning, recording, and transferring thereof? Therefore material gold or silver was unnecessary to the equation (Queries 27, 29–35). He considered paper, bills of exchange and bank notes money, its primary function being ‘credit for so much power’ to employ labour, promote industry and record profit (Queries 426–7). To support this case Berkeley presented a desert island model. Producers of surplus initially exchanged by way of credit, giving way to a convention of ‘tallies, tokens, tickets, or counters’ (Queries 46–7). Social convention was at the base of the value, or rather exchange-value, of money. Berkeley queried, then: 440. Whether paper doth not by its stamp and signature acquire a local value, and become as precious and as scarce as gold? And whether it be not much fitter to circulate large sums, and therefore preferable to gold? He (Query 445) concluded by defining progressive stages to perfection: 1) simple exchange, 2) utilising an amount of a metal as an exchange medium, 3) use of coin, and 4) creation of publicly authorised paper currency. Berkeley argued for greater popular knowledge of the significance of the central power of money as a market medium (Queries 278, 441). At the same time he suggested that altering the denomination of coins was ‘a public cheat’ (Query 28). Berkeley, like Marx, gave market actors and productive activities the greatest legitimacy when it came to the measure of value function of money. However, Marx’s sophisticated analysis embedded productive relations within a satellite sphere of circulation within which labour appeared rather like a proton, the product/commodity a neutron and money/capital an electron. From this perspective Marx (1859: 79) charged Berkeley with conflating value and price, a characteristic flaw of idealist concepts of money as well as the analyses of bourgeois economists. Whereas Macleod adopted a narrow, empirical and pragmatic banker’s view, Berkeley had a moral, philosophic and holistic framework more akin to Marx. Berkeley, like Macleod, was wary of and distanced his proposals from Lawism (Queries 254, 281ff). However, while Berkeley appreciated money for oiling the wheels of industry, he was wary of selfish greed and conspicuous consumption (Queries 217, 304–12). Berkeley believed money ought to be responsibly controlled by banks strictly to promote industry to provide work and incomes. In contrast to Marx, who developed models independent of state support or interference, Berkeley had more faith in a well-managed bank to benefit industry than in a free market with a gold mine (Queries 281–9). Here Berkeley’s hopes that a national bank would adequately provide for economic development merged with utopian socialist dreams that Marx regarded disturbing and fallacious (Queries 277, 289ff). No doubt associating Berkeley’s notions of money with the proposals of Proudhon, Gray and others, in A Contribution Marx expressed great irritation with his nominalist concept of money. He scathingly reduced Berkeley’s ‘abstract concept of value’ to a perspective of money as tokens of value that represented ‘nothing’ (Marx 1859: 79). Similarly Marx (1867:200n) criticised Lassalle’s explicitly idealist theory of money — wherein he referred to an analogy attributed to Heraclitus between fuel and fire and commodities and gold — because he ‘erroneously’ presented money as ‘a mere symbol of value’. In conclusion, Marx (1859: 78) called Berkeley ‘the advocate of mystical idealism in English philosophy’ charging him with confusing the standard of price with the measure of value and metallic money with paper tokens. 2.3 Nominalist and utopian misconceptions In Marx’s view, a focus on national monies of account misled theoreticians towards a nominalist position and Sir James Steuart had advanced most in this direction. In a quote reproduced by Marx in A Contribution (1859: 80) Steuart referred to the monetary unit as ‘an ideal scale of equal parts’, a proportion like a degree or a minute, independent of a specific commodity. Steuart viewed money as price. In contrast Marx (1859: 68) had a multi-dimensional approach arguing that capitalist commodity production and exchange had transformed the measure of value into a standard of price: ‘it is only the commensurability of commodities as materialised labour-time which converts gold into money’. For Marx bank notes and state monies had a superficial existence dependent on fundamental dynamics related to producing and circulating commodities. In the deliberately brief and select history in A Contribution, Marx (1859: 76–86) singled out John Gray for similar attention. He identified Gray—via his proposal for a central bank to issue notes according to expended labour—the progenitor of the theory of labour-time as a direct measure of value and standard of price. Marx criticised such reforms and the associated arguments of Thompson, Bray and Proudhon for their unsatisfactory analyses of money. He pointed to the Birmingham school too for falsely assuming that ‘labour-time is the substance and the inherent measure of value’ and that ‘labour-time is the real standard of money’. Indeed Gray (1848: 195) went so far as to suggest that money was ‘an instrument of destruction, compared with which gunpowder is harmless, and the sword a toy’. Money was purely a government creature and ill conceived as any kind of measure at all (Ibid: 196–7). At the same time Gray (Ibid: 198) argued for a bank to institute and manage money that was a ‘true measure of value’. Marx was irritated by the theoretical naivety underlying such suggestions. He argued that production for the market by labour demanded the existent money that was irreplaceable. Further, money was merely the value-form and not the source of the contradictions to which it gave form. In a letter to Weydemeyer, sent 1 February 1858, Marx boasted that in A Contribution: ...the Proudhonist socialism now FASHIONABLE in France — which wants to retain private production while organising the exchange of private products, to have commodities but not money — is demolished to its very foundations. (1983: 377) Thus Marx intended to make clear irreducible associations between commodities and money (and capital) in the key concepts, his money commodity and value-form. In the process Marx reduced the nominalist position to a narrow circulatory function that made the commodity dominant and even had the effect of obliterating it: The exchange-value of commodities regarded as a particular, exclusive commodity, constitutes money...Money is not a symbol, just as the existence of a use-value in the form of a commodity is no symbol. A social relation of production appears as something existing apart from individual human beings, and the distinctive relations into which they enter in the course of production in society appear as the specific properties of a thing — it is this perverted appearance, this prosaically real, and by no means imaginary, mystification that is characteristic of all social forms of labour positing exchange-value. (1859: 48–49.) 3. The money commodity Marx’s theory of the money commodity in Chapter One of Capital I (Marx 1867) argued that the exchange of commodities necessarily led to money and conversely that money had to be a commodity, the money commodity. Its value was simply recognised in circulation. The value of money was neither imaginary nor symbolic except in as much as all commodities were symbols as bearers of value. Marx’s money was the ‘necessary form of appearance of the measure of value which is immanent in commodities, namely labour-time’ (Ibid: 181, 184-6,188). In a theoretical sense money could be any commodity; in a practical sense gold or silver had clear advantages. An obvious answer to the question, ‘What is common between commodities?’ is that they are all sold for money. While nominalist and utopian views treated money like a black hole or vacant space, Marx presented money as a fundamental aspect of the commodity world ruled by his law of value. The money commodity provided a clear and direct route to labour to support his labour theory of value. To ground his theory of value and demonstrate how waged work energised capitalism, Marx made value, socially necessary labour time, distinct from price while exchange-value was expressed in terms of money, i.e. an amount of a (money) commodity. Once elaborated, this dialectical approach revealed processes that were exploitative and deceptive. Marx argued that the purchasing power of money was determined for, as well as by, the transactors as a combined effect of market forces that integrated relations of production with circulation. Neither an individual nor any collective authority could determine the value or purchasing power of money within capitalism. The function of money as a measure of value had primary significance in parallel, at one remove, with the conceptual distinction between value (production) and price (circulation). Marx’s critiques of credit or nominalist theories of money made clear his belief that money functioned to create a specific version of labour-time as the measure of value. His ‘money’ straddled the interrelationships between production and circulation. For Marx, credit money was a commercial instrument like a bill of exchange. State currency, legal tender, was distinct from credit money, and simply a token of value. Most significantly, Marx (1859: 116) defined state-issued paper legal tender as ‘an advanced form of the token of value, and the only kind of paper money which directly arises from metallic currency or from simple circulation itself’. In Marx’s view: the exchange-value of money can acquire again an existence separate from its material, from its substance, as in paper money, without, however, abolishing the privilege of this particular commodity, since the separate existence must continue to receive its denomination from the particular commodity. (1986: 104) In circulation, money validated products as commodities, a qualitative process distinct from the quantitative, i.e. the price as an amount. Price was determined socially in the broad sphere of market transactions. Certainly transactors calculated, deciding to or not to sell or buy and setting limits in price negotiations. However market prices resulted from an elaborate series of activities. Therefore Marx argued that price was not calculated via mental measure or thought form in either personal or social senses. While money was simply a ‘material sign’ and ‘conscious token’ of exchange-value, it was ‘not the execution of a preconceived idea’ (Ibid: 82). In Marx’s framework the function of money in circulation reduced to simple validation while the quantitative aspects of value were determined by a much more complex process that related back to the measure of value, to production and labour-time. 4. Abstract labour and credit theories of money The main claim of a nominalist, sign, credit, or symbol theory of money is that money is valueless in itself; the value of money is determined by its purchasing power and formed ‘in and by’ the minds of vendors and buyers. Marx opposed this idealism, as he saw it. Indeed the credit theories of money he had before him were weak, incomplete and unsatisfactory from many angles. Marx made logical associations too between nominalist approaches and quantity theorists even though this was not, for instance, how Macleod saw it. Most significantly Marx reasoned that credit theories of money ignored or warped the process whereby socially necessary labour-time evolved as the substance of the value-form. Formulations of labour-time were central to Marx’s criticisms in A Contrbution. According to him (Marx 1859: 54–55) Boisguillebert had correctly associated labourtime with the measure of value but crudely conflated exchange-value with concrete labour-time. Benjamin Franklin had more accurately associated exchange-value with abstract labour but had incorrectly deduced that money was ‘the direct embodiment of this alienated labour’ (Ibid: 57). For Marx (Ibid: 65) the universal equivalent arose in the circulation of commodities as ‘the direct reification of universal labour-time’. The measure of value and standard of price were tied together in the money commodity. The social relations of production were expressed in labour accounting in abstract labour-time (pure activity), but the exchange of commodities (past labour or objectified labour) took place in ratios of prices or equivalent amounts of a specific commodity. According to Marx (1862:138) the ‘immanent’ and ‘external’ measures of value united in an amount of the money commodity, say in an ounce of gold. The ounce of gold was the product of a definite amount of the socially necessary labour time, as well as being the universal form of exchange-value, a standard of price. The nature of the numeraire, the quality of money and its quantitative value dimensions are key to distinctions between commodity and credit theories of money. Challenges to the way Marx theorises abstract or socially necessary labour with respect to the money commodity are located here too (Nelson 1999: 187–207). Foley (undated: 9–10), for instance, has charged Marx with conflating the value of the money commodity and the value of money. To maintain the general association Marx made between money and ‘embodied labour’ — which is ‘central to the idea that money is a form of value and that the substance of value is abstract social labor’ — Foley (1982: 41) has argued for a Marxian credit theory of money in which the value of money is defined in terms of ‘the ratio of aggregate direct labour to aggregate value added’. Similarly Bellofiore (1989:9) has theorised money as ‘an institutional representation of abstract labour, i.e. it is essentially a symbol — though sometimes a use value can be its support’. Some conflicts between interpretations of Marx’s labour theory of value and his four-fold presentation of the value-form arise because the detail and complexity of his dialectical analysis all too easily suggests evolutionary developments, spatial layers d i i h h i Th d i d f f M ’ hi i d analysis to some key transition or relation continues. However, money and value are abstractions like ‘weather’, involving sensual and logical levels of knowledge. The more robust reading indicates that Marx deliberately presented his examination in a multi-dimensional manner, i.e. dialectically. Like those we live in, these dimensions exist as a compact unity, only independent in abstraction and even then only partially. In Marx’s theory of the money commodity, the value-form evolved along with the development of three dimensions that effectively formed a fourth. Marx’s valueform(s) advanced from quality to quantity to qualitative quantum and then consciousness in parallel with individual validation or determination of value per se to the social establishment of relative value and the implication of a money commodity. In as much as theoretical inconsistencies and weaknesses have been identified with Marx’s concepts of abstract value, socially necessary labour-time and a money commodity, it is the concept of the value-form that has proved more robust and permitted the development of Marxian credit theories of money. At the time Marx wrote, commodity theories of money held sway. This influenced Marx’s (1983: 396) analysis even though at hand commodity theories were not robust. Marx developed his concepts of money in opposition to Ricardo’s theory as well as crude fetish analyses that conflated gold and money. Popularly commodity theories of money seemed to fit with reality. In a superficial sense money was, ultimately, gold. The association between currencies and gold, the gold standard and the international standard of payments were offered as evidence of commodity theories of money in general and, by Marx, for a theory of the money commodity in particular. However, while the gold standard linked currencies arranged and managed on a state-by-state basis, the purely metallic money of Marx’s analytical models never existed. Ganssmann (1988) is not alone in observing that the notion of a money commodity seemed ‘at odds with everyday experience already in Marx’s times’. Similarly Vilar (1969: 344) has argued that it would ‘be quite wrong to counter-pose some imagined age of metal currency, presumed to cover the whole of previous history, to a period of modern currency which began at some point in the 1920s’. Indeed even Marx referred to the Bank of England’s reserves as ‘a mere phantom of the mind’ and was equally pressed to find ‘something solid’ in his Alice in Wonderland discussions of crises (Marx 1894: 603 and Nelson 1999: 148–52). Marx’s analysis tended towards a credit theory of money in more ways than he admitted, i.e. in his discussions of a ‘notional’ price and ‘symbolic’ coin. The insubstantial value of Marx’s hoard and associated development of money capital, reified in its abstract form as money of account in the circuits of Capital II, indicate a credit theory of money too. Most importantly the ‘value-form’ seems compatible with theories highlighting the purchasing power of money. In these theorisations money is only superficially independent of the values of circulating commodities. In short, credit theories of money using Marx’s labour theory of value as scaffolding are feasible without damaging, indeed even enhancing, theorisation of socially necessary labour-time. This is what the best of the recent reinterpretations have shown, i.e. how easily Marx’s analyses can be revised by substituting a credit theory of money. The authors of these reconstructions benefit from more advanced credit theories of money and life experience that suggests credit theories of money are plausible. Thus, Bellofiore acknowledged that Schumpeter’s work informed his revisions of Marx’s theory of money and Duménil and Lévy (1999) similarly stress the parallel interests of Marx and Schumpeter in crises, cycles and structural change. Writing sixty years after Marx’s Capital I was published, Schumpeter (1917–18) argued that money had no use-value, i.e. no intrinsic value in the way a commodity does, ‘not even when it happens to consist of a valuable material’ and integrated money in a dynamic theory of capitalist development. This and later works developed on, rather than departed from, directions indicated in Macleod, Berkeley and other works familiar to Marx. Following Macleod, money looked to the future as a ‘claim ticket’ rather than as a ‘receipt voucher’; money qua money only had an exchange-value because of its purchasing power and as a wage served as ‘pure credit’ (Schumpeter 1917–18: 161–2, 206). Marx’s analysis was designed to show how collective behaviour, not simply calculating thoughts, produced the laws of value that described the nature of the market and production for the market. His labour theory of value and theory of the money commodity demonstrated a more general claim that: It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their consciousness. (Marx 1859: 21) Neither a singular nor a state (public) authority had made money a commodity. Rather it evolved from commodity circulation and production for exchange as an obdurate social fact. Money, like capital, arose as an economic category from a complex of social relations. It was a social institution but not amenable to reform because it was only part of a complex system. It was not even the key aspect of that system but rather the focus for social reform and revolution lay with waged labour. It is clear that Marx coupled his criticisms of nominalist and utopian socialist approaches with idealist and reformist dangers. He intended to demonstrate that language associated with money implied or reproduced popular misconceptions implicated in capitalist exploitation and deception. Instead he sought to demonstrate that a peculiar version of labour-time was expressed through market transactions via money. Although the money commodity seemed a logical extension of his labour based analysis and provided a medium for his labour theory of value, in retrospect it seems he overstated his case. In as much as revisions preserve the central scaffolding of Marx’s labour theory of value, substituting credit theories of money for Marx’s money commodity seem legitimate. Here other important consistencies with Marx include recognition that the market circumscribes state action with respect to money so it cannot influence the value of money. In this way the materialist analysis remains intact along with the revolutionary implication of Marx’s profound analysis that social justice and human development require a world without state and money. ReferencesBellofiore, Riccardo 1989 ‘A Monetary Labor Theory of Value’: Review of Radical Political Economy 21 (1&2): 1–25Berkeley, Bishop George (1735–37) The Querist. Dublin.De Brunhoff, Suzanne (1973) English translation 1976 Marx on Money. New York,Urizen Books. Duménil, Gérard and Lévy, Dominique (1999) A Note on Structural Change,Economic Dynamics, and Crisis. Later version of paper for Topics in theAnalysis of Structural Change and Economic Dynamics Conference, Siena, 13-14 July 1990. Foley, Duncan 1982. ‘The Value of Money, the Value of Labor Power and theMarxian Transformation Problem ‘Review of Radical Political Economy 14 (2):37 47 —————— Undated. ‘On Marx’s Theory of Money’ Social Concept 1: 5–19.Ganssmann, Heiner (1988) ‘Money — a Symbolically Generalised Medium ofCommunication? On the Concept of Money in Recent Sociology’ Economy andSociety 17 (3): 285–316.Gray, John (1848) Excerpt from Lecturers on the Nature and Use of Money. Reprintfrom 1972 Clifton, Augustus M. Kelley Pubs edn in Jean Cartelier (1987)‘Mesure de la Valeur et Système Monétaire: la Tentative de Gray (1848). Texteset Commentaire’, Cahiers D’Économie Politique: Histoire de la Pensée etThéories 13:191–208 and excerpt: 194–205.Lipietz, Alain (1982) ‘Credit Money: A condition permitting inflationary crisis’Review of Radical Political Economics 14 (2): 49–57. ————— (1983) The Enchanted World: Inflation, Credit and the World Crisis.London, Verso.Macleod, Henry Dunning (1855) The Theory and Practice of Banking Volume I.London, Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans. —————————— (1856) The Theory and Practice of Banking Volume II.London, Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans.Marx, Karl (1859) Engl. trans. from Marx/Engels, Werke, Band XIII, Dietz Verlag,Berlin 1964, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. Moscow, Progress Publishers, 1970.———— (1867) Das Kapital, Band I, Engl. trans. by Ben Fowkes of the fourth edn(1984) Capital, Volume I. (Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1976).———— (1885) Das Kapital, Band II, Capital II. (Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1978). ———— (1894) Das Kapital, Band III, Capital III. (Harmondsworth, Penguin,1981).———— (1962) Theorien über den Mehrwert, Teil 3, Dietz Verlag, Berlin, Engl.translation by Jack Cohen and S.W. Ryazanskaya Theories of Surplus Value III. Moscow, Progress Publishers, 1971.———— (1986) in Marx, Karl and Engels, Frederick. Collected Works XXVIII; KarlMarx 1857–1861. London, Lawrence and Wishart.———— (1983) in Marx, Karl and Engels, Frederick. Collected Works XXXX; Letters January 1856—December 1859. London, Lawrence and Wishart.Nelson, Anitra (1999) Marx’s Concept of Money; the God of Commodities. LondonR l d Rubin, Isaak Il’ich ‘Abstract Labour and Value in Marx’s System’ Capital and Class5: 107–39.Schumpeter, Joseph A. (1954) History of Economic Analysis, Paperback 1986 ednLondon, George Allen and Unwin.————————— (1917–18) ‘Money and the Social Product’ InternationalEconomic Papers 6: 148–211.Skaggs, Neil T. (1997) ‘Henry Dunning Macleod and the Credit Theory of Money’ inCohen, A. Hageman, H. and Smithin, J. (eds) Money, Financial Institutions andMacroeconomics. Boston, Kluwer Academic Publishers: 109–23.Vilar, Pierre (1969) A History of Gold and Money 1450–1920. London, New LeftBooks.

برای دانلود رایگان متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Marx’s Theory of Money in Historical Perspective

The paper considers two problems related to Marx’s theory of money: first, the definition and measurement of the quantity of social labor time represented by a unit of money; second, the application of Marx’s commodity-money theory to contemporary monetary institutions based on state-credit money. In theory social labor time and the price expression of exchange value emerge simultaneously, so t...

متن کامل

From the Gold Standard to the Floating Dollar Standard: An Appraisal in the Light of Marx’s Theory of Money

The paper explores the insights offered by Marx’s analysis of the emergence of “world money” into the workings of the international gold standard period and the post-Bretton Woods floating dollar standard. In a curious inversion of the traditional formulations drawing on Lenin, imperial hegemony in today’s context would seem to be associated with net capital imports (rather than exports) by the...

متن کامل

Inside the capital circuit: what money is and what it does

One view, argued by Williams (2000), is that Marx simply made a ‘category mistake’ when he introduced commodity money into his theory of value. If money is fully determined by its social functions in capitalism then the physical characteristics assumed by money become historically contingent so that ‘commodity-money is necessary neither to the logic of Marx’s system nor to the logic of capitali...

متن کامل

Division of Labor and Structuration Theory: A Comparative and Theoretical Analysis of Marx’s and Durkheim’s Theories as the Early Approaches to Structuration Theory

To the extent that a society is to work, there exist a need for a cooperative process, including Weber’s and Merton’s note of common means and goals. But at the same time, there exist no societal process without involving conflict; (conflict in a dynamic and dialectical sense.) Dealing with this problematic situation the emergence of “division of labor”, as a compulsive social differentiation, ...

متن کامل

Endogeneity of Money and the State in Marx’s theory of Non-commodity Money

Moseley and Saros’s MELT in case of inconvertible paper money In developing Marx’s non-commodity theory of money which is largely an uncultivated area in Marxian economics, one of the crucial issues at stake is to establish the monetary expression of labour time (MELT) in case of inconvertible paper money consistently with Marx’s theory in general and not rejecting his labour theory of value in...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2003